A good commentary on Pindar’s odes will give due weight to a number of elements: rhetoric, historical background, sport, mythology, metre, grammar and syntax. P.’s massive commentaries, each prefaced by 40+ pages of ‘interpretation’, cover all these elements with thoroughness and imagination. They will need to be consulted by anyone considering these three odes. Sadly, however, the text has not been sufficiently edited and revised before publication: it is repetitive, too long, and full of mistakes which the editors of these Mnemosyne Supplements should never have allowed to appear.
The general introduction, and the commentaries themselves, take their starting point from the assumption that ‘Because of the occasional nature of the genre [= every ode is a response to a specific event], every single Pindaric victory ode is firmly rooted in its own historical setting’ (3). No one will argue with that, but P. then goes further: his work goes beyond that of other Pindarists ‘in that it does not only seek to reconstruct the historical setting of individual odes but also attempts to explain how the individual odes functioned as epinicia within the context of their historical setting, and how they did so as coherent wholes’ (12). Here we are on dangerous ground, as rarely is it possible to reconstruct anything that one could plausibly call ‘the historical setting’. But P. is a bold interpreter: N. 3.17-18
On N. 5.11-16 (Peleus, Telamon and Phocus praying together at the altar of Zeus Hellenius on Aegina that the island be noble in men and renowned in ships), ‘The association of the solidarity of the three Aeacids with the prosperity of Aegina as a whole suggests the passage is meant to have a relevance to the [sic] Aeginetan society. It can be understood as an illustration of the thought that concord is preferable to internal conflict and thus as a recommendation to the Aeginetan audience not to turn against one another’ (65-6). And in the light of the internal Aeginetan unrest and bloodshed which P. thinks took place about the time the ode was performed (487 BC) and which in his view is implied in the allusion to in the murder of Phocus by his half-brothers Peleus and Telemon, P. concludes that Pindar’s presentation ‘makes sense if his objective were to reconcile the dmow with the aristocratic rulers’ (67). If P. were right about this, it would give to this ode a political purpose rather different from that entertained by most Pindarists hitherto.
P.’s historicising is more persuasive when applied to P. 8 with its overtly political opening address to
P. disagrees with Snell-Maehler’s Teubner (8th edition) text in 25 places, including five where he prefers not to ‘normalise’
However, he gives a persuasive interpretation of what is perhaps the most problematic passage in all of the three odes, the ‘epiphany’ of Alcmaeon at P. 8.56-60 (pp. 436-8 and 540-5): what Pindar says about Alcmaeon is tailored to bring out the role of inherited qualities, a point of relevance to the victor (35-7); and there is a careful discussion of the difficult N. 5.43.
But 238 lines of text did not require a book of more than 700 pages; it should have been reduced to less than half that length. Several times whole chunks are repeated word for word (e.g. p.74 n.23 = p.155 n.139, 81 n.38 is on pp.176-7, 200 n.6 is in 241 n.5); there is overlap between the substantial ‘interpretations’ to each ode and the commentaries and the 61-page appendix. Some comments are plain silly and self-indulgent: N. 5.49