This slim new volume adds yet another useful title to Hackett’s collection of books related to presocratic philosophy. This growing library of both new and reprinted works includes volumes on individual authors, such as M. R. Wright’s monograph on Empedocles (1981; repr. 1995) and Charles Kahn’s on Anaximander (1962; repr. 1994), more general treatments such as Edward Hussey’s The Presocratics (1995) and Richard McKirahan’s Philosophy Before Socrates (1994), and the anthology Readings in Ancient Greek Philosophy, edited by S. Marc Cohen, Patricia Curd, and C. D. C. Reeve (1995). In fact, this last work forms the basis of this new volume: A Presocratics Reader is in essence a fascicle, amounting to Part One (“slightly revised and expanded” according to the preface) of Readings in Ancient Greek Philosophy.
Clearly the book is intended for use in undergraduate survey courses in philosophy, ancient philosophy, or Greek civilization. Unlike Kirk, Raven and Schofield’s The Presocratic Philosophers (2nd ed., Cambridge, 1983) or McKirahan’s Philosophy Before Socrates, APR contains a bare minimum of notes and commentary. Instead, its aim is to let the (translated) words of the philosophers speak for themselves. Therefore in terms of scope and price its main competitors in the market will be Kathleen Freeman’s Ancilla to the Presocratic Philosophers (Harvard, 1957, $11.95) and Jonathan Barnes’Early Greek Philosophy (Penguin, 1987, $10.95).
Readers and classroom instructors will appreciate several aspects of this new volume. Most welcome of all will be the excellent translations by McKirahan.
The book does suffer, however, from some deficiencies and unfortunate omissions. Although the publisher’s promotional flier for APR praises as a strength the book’s “unobtrusive, minimally interpretive editorial material,” I nevertheless think that the editor would have done well to risk intruding a bit more. It is unclear to what extent the problem is attributable to a lack of editorial attentiveness or to an impatient publisher performing a quick cut-and-paste job in order to rush the book into print.
First, although APR sometimes includes short discussions of key vocabulary in the headnotes for various authors and schools, no glossary or appendix discussing terminology, philosophical and otherwise, is added. Our editor could have utilized additional explanatory footnotes in lieu of a glossary, but these, too, are lacking. For example, in APR’s Milesians fragment 18 for Anaximenes (DK A7), we have the line, “Cloud results from air through felting, and water when this happens to a greater degree.” In his own book McKirahan included a short footnote on “felting”, but this is not carried over with his translation into APR. Second, APR has no indexes: there is neither an index of source passages nor a general index of names and subjects. Third, the introductory sections are wanting in several respects. For instance, we receive only a select rather than a complete treatment of the sources for the fragments. Also, the preface lacks a “Guide to the Reader” section to explain the typography: What is the uninitiated reader to infer when he or she sees words or phrases within pointed brackets, square brackets, and regular parentheses?
More importantly, perhaps, the introduction fails to set the right tone for the presentation of the fragments which follow. As an introductory-level text APR does surprisingly little to inform the reader about the many textual problems and pitfalls of the fragments.
One of these decisions concerns the question of whether to include the immediate context of each fragment. The editor of APR has chosen not to do this. Although this decision results in a more straightforward and unencumbered view of the fragments on the page than one gets (for instance) in Barnes, at the same time it has some unfortunate consequences. For example, it eliminates the opportunity for understanding how the source authors understood the fragments, and so eliminates a tool we might have used to improve our own understanding of them. Moreover, without their contexts the nature of the extant evidence for the fragments is hidden: Does the source author seem to be paraphrasing or quoting directly? Where exactly does the source author leave off and the actual fragment begin? The problem is especially acute for the Milesians, since the lone fragment of Anaximander, the only primary source for Milesian philosophy, must be extricated from a lost work of Theophrastus repeated by Simplicius.
Once the determination has been made about what material to include, the next area of decision concerns translation. The translations of the fragments in APR are uniformly of high quality. Due to the vexed status of many fragments, however, a fundamental question for any translator is what text or variants should be read. It is not exactly clear what position the editor of APR takes on this issue. There are scattered about a few very brief asterisked footnotes which indicate a decision one way or another regarding a specific textual reading. But most of these notes have been imported along with the translations; one is at a loss to discern any guiding principle behind what gets noted and what does not. In any case, the editor may as well have eliminated all these notes, for what they are worth. For example, APR’s Pluralists fragment 35 (Empedocles DK B16) includes the footnote, “Reading Esti gar hôs paros ên (Lloyd-Jones).” How this will help the reader (especially a Greekless reader in an introductory class), I do not know. The editor does not indicate what else might have been read, nor are we given any further information about what Lloyd-Jones’ role in all this is or where to go to find out. The problem is that Curd has incorporated McKirahan’s note without McKirahan’s supporting commentary and bibliography. The story is generally the same for the few remaining footnotes.
Turning now to the question of how Curd’s APR compares with its competitors by Freeman and Barnes, it appears that a preference may hinge on where one draws the line between what is “helpful but unobtrusive editorial material” and helpful but cumbrous material. By deciding to do so little—in this reviewer’s eyes, too little—APR is most similar in format to Freeman’s Ancilla to the Presocratic Philosophers. Although Freeman’s Ancilla is more comprehensive than APR’s“selected” fragments, the selection in APR is judicious and thorough enough that instructors are not likely to require any of the fragments that have been left out. More significantly, however, the superior quality of APR’s translations ought to turn former Ancilla buyers into eager APR purchasers. Persons looking for more exegesis and aids to the reader may prefer Barnes’ Penguin edition of the presocratics. Barnes manages to include most of the features which are wanting in APR, such as indexes, a complete treatment of the sources, a guide to the typography, the immediate context for each fragment, and a very helpful and thorough introduction. At the same time, rather than embedding the fragments within his own extended commentary, he still maintains as his focus the words of the philosophers themselves. Yet in terms of range (i.e., having the section of fragments from the sophists) and cost, many instructors may prefer APR.
APR offers a useful and inexpensive resource for instructors in philosophy or Greek civilization courses wishing to introduce their students to these engaging and influential thinkers. But I hope that we soon will see a second edition of APR which incorporates many of the components this current edition lacks, components which will make the book even more useful for both the instructor and student.